Experience
– Mystical Experience
In this article, “Experience”, by
Robert H Sharf, the idea of experience
as it relates to religious experience and
mystical experience is discussed. The
definition of the term experience is complex in general and even more complex
for a term such as “mystical experience” that I would like to discuss in this
brief essay as I focus on the idea of mystical experience. First I will give a
brief overview of mystical experiences as described in this article. Then I
will give my critical view as it relates to the argumentation that the author
offers in the article, specifically I would argue the difficulty in describing
or studying experiences that are not personal. As I reiterate the point that
the author makes regarding the difficulty of relating experiences, I question
the possibility of an outsider approach to the investigation of experiences,
using the examples of Vipassana and Zen meditation that the author uses as an
example of distinct practices.
A “mystical experience is generally construed as a direct encounter
with the divine or the absolute” claims the author, “and, as such, the “raw
experience” is not affected by linguistics, cultural or historical
contingencies” (p 96) or at least so do both perennialists as well as their
critics claim. For Sharf the debate that those scholars concerned with mysticism
are having centers on the issue of whether the experience is colored by the background of the experiencer or whether
it is the description of the experience
is colored by the background of the experiencer, and as such in the author’s
opinion the scholars of mysticism are missing the most important question of
what in fact is the experience and whether the experience even can be accepted
as such given the lack of scientific evidence and proof. “Scholars of mysticism
are content to focus on the distinctive characteristics and the philosophical
implications […] of religious or mystical experiences without pausing to
consider what sort of thing experience may be in the first place.” (p 103)
The question of what experience is
becomes central. As I read the opinion of Sharf regarding the nature of mystical experience, I can see how it
becomes challenging to allow for accounts, no matter how similar, frequent, and
common they may be, to be received by the critical mind and the necessity to
question if they are valid and plausible. Sharf attempts to define the word
experience as what is “simply given to us in the immediacy of each moment of
perception” (p 104). I question though his attempt to limit experience to what
it is that the scholars would like
experience to serve when he attempts to define what is experience in
ostensive terms. Why would experience have to serve a purpose, much more
importantly the purpose of the scholar to define it as such? As Shaft suggests
though, the academic “allure of the rhetoric of experience in the modern period
[for] both Western theologians and secular scholars” is very real. His
reasoning of is grouped into two categories: empiricism and cultural
pluralism.” Empiricism centers on the idea that “all truth claims must be
subject, in theory and not in fact, to empirical or scientific verification”.
Cultural pluralism centers on the idea that “by claiming to make sense of the
transcended then all religious traditions could lay some claim to the truth”.
(p.95-96) The goal of the theologians and the secular scholars seems laudable
and in fact remains a field of open investigation.
The author expresses that “indeed I
sympathize with the difficulty that mystics have in expressing themselves, the problem
of conceptualizing that which transcends all concepts”. It is in my opinion that
by nature these experiences are inexpressible. There seems to be a parallel
almost reality that sometimes mystics are allowed to experience and yet in that
reality even if consciousness remains active, the mystic is no longer able to
express the vastness of his or her experience. Indeed many mystics express that
words are not enough, and often they choose to speak in metaphors, in
parabolas, in poetic forms or a combination of the above (James). Experiences
can even be shared and yet each person can only describe his or her perception
of what has occurred, sometimes only sharing a general sense of characteristics
in the experience. Mystical experiences are a window to some essential truth.
An insight to the polemic that Sharf
describes in terms of defining the experience is that of talking about
experiences that one has not yet or may never have. I found it interesting that
since I have not had the experience of Theravada Vipassana or Zen meditation I
would not for example be able to fully appreciate the dialectic used to
describe the experiences. In fact I have read a paper relating Vipassana
meditation to mystical experiences (Hubina). In Hubina’s paper I was able to
follow the linguistic argumentation, I was able to successfully relate the
readings to my experiences or to accounts of other’s experiences or to other
reading. Yet I was not able to relate
to the experiences described and thus if I now have to express an opinion on
whether Vipassana mediation can lead to mystical experiences I find myself
wondering what it is that would qualify me to offer such an opinion. For that I
would have to rely on a third party account of what happens, in this case a
scholar who himself relies on the accounts of others. This brings an important
question to the argumentation of whether or not relating experiences of others
can be done. This is typically the case that in experiences that require time,
that can be sometimes measured in years, it may not be possible for the
researcher to acquire deep personal experiences, if such deep and
transcendental personal experiences can even be acquired. How do we reconcile
then the world of academia and the world of spiritual practices? Can we find a
common language and bridges of communication? This would be an important
challenge to overcome for the academic investigation of mystical experiences.
Last, to the point that Sharf makes
that there is no consensus either in the “designation of the particular states
of consciousness [and also] in the psychotropic techniques used to produce them
(samatha versus vipassana) [and that] belies the notion that the rhetoric of
meditative experience functions ostensively.” (p 107) I would propose that that
mystical experiences do follow a cookie cutter approach. These experiences
represent partially a connection with something possible superhuman, that one
can choose to call God.
In conclusion, it seems that
philosophically as well as practically the word experience is charged with reasons to rationally contest such
claims. The question of whether there is something additional to discuss
remains open. Shaft proposes a view that it is because of the usefulness in
academia that experiences are investigated. James and his followers propose
that it is because these experiences point to some truth that this
investigation is necessary. What I am finding is that any outside observer
would have difficulty reporting regarding such experiences. It may be a
possibility though that no matter how careful investigation is and how many
attempts the researchers makes into defining and establishing a universal truth
that precisely this universality as it relates to experience would keep eluding
the researchers’ efforts because of the very nature of mystical experiences.
References
James,
William (1902) The Varieties of Religious
Experiences: A Study in Human Nature, Being the Gifford Lectures on Natural
Religion Delivered at Edinburgh in 1901–1902 Longmans Green Co.
Hubina,
Milos “Mysticism and Theravada Meditation” working
paper
Shaft,
Ronald H “Experience” in Critical Terms
for Religious Studies (1998) edited by Taylor, Mark C. The University of
Chicago Press.
No comments:
Post a Comment