What is religion - a comparative answer
The two questions that scholars of religion are primarily
concerned with when asked to explore the question of “what is religion”, and
for the purposes of this essay I would limit the meaning of this question to
the definition of religion, are the origins of religion and the persistence of
religion. To answer these two questions early theorists proposed the
essentialist theories. Essentialist theories focus on the content of religion
and that beliefs have a reason to exist because there is an essence underlying
the presence of religion. Whether or not there is an essence to religion and
what this essence may be is the important theoretical question because it would
explain both the existence as well as the persistence of religion. Wilfred
Cantwell Smith boldly stated that “one might almost say that the concern with
the religious man is with God; the concern with the observer is with religion”.
In this essay I will explore the evolution of the term religion in the last century, limiting myself to the evolution from
the point of of the essentialists (specifically James George Frazier, Edward Burnett
Tylor and later Mircea Eliade) comparing and contrasting it with the points of
view of Wilfred Cantwell Smith and Jonathan Z. Smith. In this essay I attempt
to answer the question regarding the difference in the approach and
methodologies amongst the perspective of these scholars, or theorists to be
more precise. Specifically I will explore the answers given to the central
question between essentialists and their critics of whether there is an essence
to religion and what this essence may be according to their theories.
The essentialist Edward Burnett Tylor focusses on the idea
that religion provides an explanation to the religious actor of phenomena that
would otherwise be unexplainable, so to the religious actor the essential
nature of religion is explanatory. Tylor defined religion as “a belief in
spiritual beings.” He determined that belief originated in natural phenomena. He
theorized that religion was an attempt to explain life and death, and that it
was in death and dreams that primitive people saw the supernatural, and their dreams
were the key to their spiritua understanding. And in league with his time and
the theories of evolution, Tylor theorized that as primitives evolved into
monotheists, and then today into scientists, so did beliefs and religion. Tylor’s
theory does not extend to encompass the answer to the question of the
persistence of religion in a world that uses scientific explanations as is
today’s world.
His contemporary follower and equally famous essentialist
Frazier did additionally distinguish between magic and religion, adding that
the essential nature of magic is to provide a means to influence the world of
the primitive through magic laws and ritual. So for Frazier on the one hand
religion is a pleading relationship of the religious actors to the often
anthropomorphic deities, and on the other hand magical beliefs restore the
control of life to the religious actor through the performance of magical
rituals. For Frazier belief holds
intrinsic value in and of itself. For Tylor and Frazier religion holds the
essential quality of providing a value to the religious actor, and so religion
is distinct from God because religion is the belief in God.
What I would like to contrast to the views of these two
essentialists is the view proposed by Wilfred Cantwell Smith. In his classic
book “The Meaning and End of Religion” Wilfred Cantwell Smith
explores the idea that the word “religion”
did not take its present, almost assumed, meaning until the last century. Part
of the disagreement over the meaning of the word comes certainly from
historical developments, and the etymological origin of the word can be traced
back Christianity. So what Wilfred Cantwell Smith proposes is that the question
of what religion means should instead be the question what it is that the word “religion” means. This has been and is
still a raging debate in religious science. Willdred Cantwell Smith boldly
suggests to eliminate the term: “my own suggestion is the word, and the
concepts, should be dropped – at least in all but the first personalist sense. I
suggest that the term “religion” is confusing, unnecessary and distorting” (p
52). His suggestion is of course only a desperate solution: when there is a
problem avoid the problem instead of offering a solution. Eliminating the word religion does not seem to me
practical, or constructive for that matter. In the same argument since we do
not agree exactly on what the word God means we should eliminate God. Or in a
more practical term, if we cannot agree what marriage is we should eliminate
marriage? I find that there are other approaches to the problem of definition
that simply eliminating the word due to the absence of an ostensive definition.
In a critical
evaluation of Wilfred Cantwell Smith’s book, Talal Asad (2001) evaluates the
attempt by Wilfred Cantwell Smith to question the nature of religion by denying
that religion has any essence as an attempt of rejection of the essentialism of
religion,. “The argument is that no thing
corresponds, properly speaking, to the noun religion. The use of that term to
refer to what does exist – namely, personal quality of faith – inevitably
reifies the term.” Wilfred Cantwell Smith suggests that the adjective
religious, as opposed to the noun form religion, escapes the danger of
reification because it refers to a quality. “The rejection of essentialism
appears not to be qualified. There is, after all, something essential that the
term religion has been used to identify”. Wilfred Cantwell Smith notes from a
historical perspective that “man is everywhere and has always been what we call
today religious”. I also find that the term religion is vague but it does hold
an essential quality of pointing to the very real and very present worship and
various rituals around the world of religious actors. I would like to close
this part of the essay with a chuckle: the criticized methodology of the “armchair
theorists” Tylor and Frazier can only be compared to that of the linguistic
historical investigation of Wilfred Cantwell Smith.
In the second part of this essay I consider the theories of
another essentialist Mircea Eliade, whose essentialist claims for religion focus
on the idea of the quest of the religious actor to find a link to the outwardly
perfection, of his quest for meaning. And while the aforementioned
essentialists looked for similar beliefs and practices in all societies, theorizing
mostly from the primitive savages regardless of time and place, Eliade focuses
on the patterns of sacred time and of sacred space. As
a historian of religion Eliade used the concepts of sacred time and sacred
space as the two proposed drivers that aid in both the origin and the
persistence of religion. This is the axis mundi around which religion is
built and where religion functions “on its own terms”, where it can in fact be
explained historically through phenomenology and through symbolism.The intense
desire of the people to imitate God comes from a desire that archaic people
have not only to mirror the realm of the sacred, but to actually be in it, and
for Eliade there stems the essential nature of religion.
Eliade offered a
natural explanation on how the fabric of society is woven with religion. He may
or may not have succeeded in making the study of religion a phenomenological
and historical enterprise, using comparison in hugely varied time and space
events and theories. For him the symbol was
the link between the sacred and the profane. This concept of the “axis mundi”
that he professes, may simply be put into the “map” of the “time” does seem to
in fact to provide a basis for an essential nature of religion itself. Eliade,
in studying comparative religion and societies, offered the concept that
religion provided meaning and contact with the sacred in history through the understanding and expression of sacred time
and space.
The theorist I contrast with the views of Mircea Eliade, a
self-professed historian of religion, although in my view so much more than
that, would be the views of Jonathan Z. Smith. Eliade proposed
a model of sacred time and sacred space to begin the conversation in a
scientific way that religion is its own justification. The early critics
attacked Eliade as a theologian even though he never expressed his own personal
opinion, since for a scientist he seemed to bring respect towards the concept
of the sacred itself. As Eliade’s student and later his critic, Jonathan Z.
Smith (1972) proclaims that “for Eliade, the Sacred, and sacred space and time
in particular, is the extraordinary, the realm in which the sacred
paradoxically manifests itself through hierophanies, kratophanies and the like.
The profane is the ordinary, the neutral, the realm of the adiaphora, the
irruptive element experienced by the religious man as non-homogenous a
breakthrough in the normal ontological levels [that] allows the possibility of
reifying or sacralizing the profane.” “There is nothing that is inherently or
essentially clean or unclean, sacred or profane. There are situational or
relational categories, mobile boundaries which shift according to the map being
employed.” In religious studies, as we try to find a scientific way to address
the motivation, basis and understanding of religion, and of its essential
nature, the question to define and contain in a particular time and space,
calling it sacred, the feeling and possibly the reality of connectedness that
is generated through religion and in fact transcends those boundaries is
limiting for Jonathan Z. Smith. So, for Jonathan Z. Smith these boundaries are
both artificial and mobile.
Jonathan Z.
Smith’s views evolved past the views of Eliade. I already gave an example of the
critique that Jonathan Z Smith brings specifically to Eliade for the concepts
of sacred time and space, that he himself considers as fluid boundaries. What
really created a drift though was Jonathan Z Smith’s now famous statement “There is no data for religion. Religion
is solely the creation of the scholar’s study. It is created for the scholar’s
analytic purposes by his imaginative acts of comparison and generalization.
Religion has no independent existence apart from the academy.” Jonathan Z Smith
with this bold and copiously documented opening statement to his book Imagining religion, referenced his opinion
by offering scores of “e.g.” of human behavior from across the globe and
throughout time, mirroring the critique to the essentialists that Wilfred
Cantwell Smith proposes. Whereas it is true that this statement would place
Jonathan Z. Smith solidly in the critics of essentialism, he has had the chance
to offer opinions that vary greatly throughout his long academic career.
In terms of the
methodology of the last two scholars explored, namely Mircea Eliade and
Jonathan Z. Smith I would jokingly also remark that their investigation was not
focused on fieldwork, rather that their prolific writing was based on
investigation of scholarship. I would
add though that the anecdotal account (2004) of Jonathan Z. Smith’s interest in
agrostology informs us of his lifelong interest in classification and taxonomy
and in fact his other interests include incongruity and difference,
generalization and description, and translation, focusing on “the insistence on
the cognitive power of distortion, along with the concomitant choice of the map
over the territory”. This systematic juxtaposition and “exaggeration in the
direction of the truth” place him close also to the direction of Edward Barnett
Tylor’s methodology (1996).
In conclusion,
this adventure in the exploration through time and space of the question of the
definition of the term religion, led me to question whether today the questions
surrounding the term religion have changed. Over time the focus shifted from whether
the essentialists’ explanations can shed light as to the question of the
existence and persistence of religion, to the question of whether there is at
all an essential nature of religion. And in answer to the suggestion of eliminating the word religion as
suggested by Wilfred Cantwell Smith, or to the statement that religion has no value except to the
academics, offer enough of a counterargument to the essentialists claim, I
showed that these two argument are really arguments over the usage of the word.
In a purely academic context we can dissect the word and find it problematic.
Yet if I walk down the street and ask ‘what is your religion” people would
gladly offer “Buddhism”, “Islam”, “Christianity”, etc. as the answer. So even
though I honor the scholarship and the scholars themselves who find that
“religion is dead” I would like to propose that we do not discard this old
friend or foe, rather I propose we continue to explore our relationship with
the word, and with the concept, further. To answer the question of the
existence and persistence of religion. I do believe that even though the answer
to this question may not be very clear, it is a lot clearer that it was a
century ago.
References:
Asad, Talal (February 2001) “Reading a Modern Classic:
Wifred Cantwell Smith’s “The Meaning and End of Religion” History Of Religions Vol 40. No 3, pp 205-222. The University of
Chicago Press
Eliade, Micrea
(1949) The Sacred and the Profane. Harvest
Book, New York.
Pals, Daniel (2006) Eight
Theories on Religion Oxford University Press
Pals, Daniel (2008) Introducing
Religion Oxford University Press
Segal, Robert A. (2005) “Theories of Religion” in The Routledge Companion to the Study of
Religion edited by Hinnel, John R. Routledge, NY
Smith, Jonathan
Z. (1972) The Wobling Pivot. The
Journal of Religion, The University of Chicago Press. vol 52 No 2 pp 134-149.
Smith, Jonathan
Z. (1982) Imagining Religion. University
of Chicago Press
Smith, Jonathan
Z. “Nothing Human in Alien to Me” (1992) in Relating
Religion: Essays in the Study of Religion (2004) University of Chicago
Press
Smith, Wilfred Cantwell (1962) The Meaning and End of Religion Macmillian New York
No comments:
Post a Comment